Since the October Revolution, Marxism has experienced almost as many crises as capitalism itself. Crises are Marxismâs bread and butter, if not its chalk and cheese. Meltdowns of capitalism usually come as little surprise to savvy Marxist theorists, whoâd seen it all coming long ago, even while those capitalist economies basked in booming glory. But economic crises are one thing; economic crisis plus a global pandemic is something else again, beyond an everyday capitalist norm, more akin to the political-economy of wartime. And for a thought that fuses theory and praxis, pandemic, like war, threatens not only life and limb, but also solidarity and tender acts of human togetherness.
But thereâs another aspect to pandemic as well as to a Marxism of pandemic: the delicate balance between the individual and society is disrupted, between a liberty at the personal level and the needs of a society at the population levelâthe scale of much epidemiological enquiry. Pandemics necessitate that public health exigencies assume priority, even at the expense of the liberty of the person. Willy-nilly, collective rights find themselves clashing with individual rights, and not always to everyoneâs likingâespecially in lands where personal freedom is touted as sacrosanct. Weâve seen this most starkly expressed in the conflict over face-mask wearing, where protecting other people is seen by some as a downshifting of the self, as an assault on individual liberty.
For the theoretically-minded, this strikes as another way to frame debates about agency versus structure, about freedom versus necessity, about which is the more important, the determinant rather than determined. Marxists might recognise such a dialectic as a rerun of debates that raged throughout the sixties and seventies about humanist versus anti-humanist Marxism, about whether subjectivity ought to prevail over objectivity; or whether Marxist history is really objective, a process without a subject, a theory more amenable to the affirmation of collective necessity.
Humanists like Henri Lefebvre (1901-1991) suggest Marxism should celebrate what Hegel called a âfreedom of subjectivity,â that it should prioritise the free will aspect of Marxâs vision, his yearning for âan association in which the free development of each is the condition for the free development of all.â The young, romantic Marxâs Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts are particularly dear to the humanist Marxistâs heart. Here, in 1844, still smitten by Hegelian idealism, the concept of alienation dominatesâor rather dis-alienationâthe transcending of alienation, the freeing of human beings from capitalist enslavement, from wage labour. Marx posits a âtotal manâ as the liberated person, as subject and object finding unity, rediscovering inner human essence, the ability for people to realise a limitless variety of possible individualities.1
For anti-humanists like Louis Althusser (1918-1990) this reasoning rings out bogus, as something ideological, problematic for any socialist ambition. Socialism needs a âscientificâ concept, says Althusser. âHumanismâ here presupposes an âempiricism of the subject,â a kind of âessenceâ to human beings, which, Althusser reckons, the mature Marxâthe Marx from the mid-1850s onwardsârejects. Humanism throws a âuniversalâ veil over society, whereas revolutionary struggle isnât a struggle to liberate âhumankindâ as such, but a struggle between classes. So, if we should ever talk about humanism, says Althusser, we might at least talk about âclass humanism,â or âproletarian humanism.â Marxist liberation isnât about releasing any transcendental human essence, nor expressive of personal freedom; itâs a historical phase that ends class exploitation, that builds democracy for the working classes.2
Humanist Marxists accuse anti-humanists of dogmatismâof endorsing an âofficialâ Marxism, under Stalinâs watch, with its programme of âthe dialectics of nature.â Class struggle therein is seen as objective and deterministic, unfolding without conscious human agency, almost behind the backs of real people, like waves eroding the shoreline. Dogmatic Marxists, Lefebvre says, are happy to move people aside, being especially leery of Marxâs early writings. After all, they might give Soviet workers dangerous ideas about alienation in their own society. But if world communism is inevitable, an inexorable act of nature, as Stalin insists, people can be readily expunged from making history; Marxism elides into economism. Everything elseâsociology, psychology, speculative philosophy, etc.âis reformist, irredeemably bourgeois.
Anti-humanists reckon the problem with dogmatism is too much humanism, not too little. Humanism encourages âthe cult of personality,â says Althusser, the agency accorded to glorious leaders who supposedly make history all by themselves, like Stalinâor Hitler and Mussolini, or like a few of our own contemporary despots. This is divine worship of the individual, subjective humanism sneaking in through the back door, ideologically poisoning the rest of the house. The cult of personality has no place in Marxist theory, Althusser says, which is why he posits the provocative thesis that Marxists should break with the idealist category of âsubject.â History has a âmotor,â according to Althusser, but no subject. âIndividuals arenât âfreeâ and âconstitutiveâ subjects in the philosophical sense of these terms,â he says. âThey work in and through the determinations of the forms of historical existence of the social relations of production and reproduction.â Itâs another way of repeating Marxâs oft-cited dictum, that the masses make their own history, but not under circumstances chosen by individuals themselves.
***
Lefebvre and Althusser, as budding opposites, joined the French Communist Party (PCF) as young men. The former, scared by the Great War, in 1925; the latter, inspired by militant Resistants, in 1948. Lefebvre would, for âideological deviations,â get expelled in 1958, though heâd reembrace the Party in the 1970s; Althusser would never leave, yet remained an outspoken critic. As dissident Party members, Lefebvreâs Marxism bathed in sunlight, was energised by what Ernst Bloch called a utopian âwarm streamâ; Althusserâs assumed a darker, colder, more melancholy cast. Lefebvreâs sixty-odd books overflow with the loose spontaneity and passion his Marxism advocates; Althusserâs writings, by contrast, are essays, tight and concise, shorn of frills.
Althusserâs anti-humanism insists that Marxism beds itself down in âthe concrete analysis of a concrete situation.â3 But Lefebvreâs humanism doesnât want to give up the ghostâgeistâof alienation. If progressives jettison it, he says, wonât the living baby disappear with the stagnant bathwater? And yet, maybe twenty-first-century Marxism needs to loosen alienation from its subjective moorings, where it can degenerate into subjectivism, into an expression of bourgeois individuality and freedom. Maybe we need to see alienation not as undermining some abstract human essence, but posit it concretely, as a historical category, at work and in life. The traits of Marxâs factory system have entered into the generic traits of our society writ large. Life itself nowadays assumes a kind of industrial logic, with speed-ups and intensity drives, drills and efficiency targets, audits and assessments. As workers lean in, as they fill in those leaky non-workday pores, alienation is concrete. It moves with the times and so should we. It takes on meaning in different epochs, changes as we change, as our needs and aspirations change, as they change us, as we change them.
Decades ago, witnessing many German and European workers opt for fascism, vote against their class interests, Lefebvre spoke of alienation as mystified consciousness, recognising how propaganda transformed peopleâs minds en masse. He never saw this morph into social media, into misinformation and fake news, into twenty-first century estrangement, whose ideological channels never switch off and span the entire planet. Our alienation is different now, more cunning, less evident. And our consciousness is different, too, reshaped and re-mystified by a culture deliberately intent on undermining peopleâs capacity to think critically, to analyse broadly and deeply. Bombarded with banal messages and commercial stimuli, our brain cells have been pulverised by informational overload. Differentiating truth from falsity becomes increasingly difficult, fertile terrain for cults of personality to prosper, for demagogues to make promises theyâll never keep. But no matter.
Here, Althusserâs analysis still shines light on the murky zones of ideology. Ideology is never just free-floating, says Althusser, never simply (or complexly) a system of ideas innocent in life. Rather, ideology gets âmateriallyâ constituted, is embedded in particular capitalist âapparatusesâ that manufacture it, that transmit it. They stalk the public, statist sectorâin education and law, in the police and army, in religious institutions and political partiesâas well as civil societyâin business and advertising, on TV and radio, in newspapers, in social media and information technology. In fact, everywhere, we are enveloped in ideology. State ideological apparatuses can act repressively, through force (sending in the police and military), or else engineer compliance via consent, via more subtle modes of domination.
Althusser says ideological apparatuses âinterpellateâ people, âhailâ us as concrete class subjects. It all happens, he says, along the lines of the most commonplace everyday sceneâa hailing from across the street: âHey, you there!â Conscious weâve done something wrong, we look over, get taken in, believe the caller. Somehow, instinctively, we listen, accept it is us being called. This is how reality takes place through ideology, Althusser says, even if it seems to take place outside of ideology, beyond it. This is how we get ârecruitedâ as class subjects and why Marx says life conditions consciousnessâand not the other way around. What Lefebvre calls mystified consciousness, Althusser terms âan imaginary representation of our real conditions of existence.â
Ideology isnât false consciousness: itâs real, has real anchoring to reality, real material existence. The bluster of Trump or Boris Johnson interpellates large numbers of people because their calls have what Althusser labels âa recognition function,â something a person needs to believe, wants to believe, recognises. It hits a reality buzzer somewhere inside them, becomes the necessary mood music for dissatisfied and alienated people. They want to hear this music, are open to it, feel the need to believe it. Itâs on the level of feeling that messages get through, stoke up visceral emotions. Yet recognition functions through illusory representations, through imaginary distortions of actual reality (like the notion the Presidential election was rigged). âExperience shows,â says Althusser, âthat the practical telecommunications of hailing is such that they hardly ever miss their man.â Verbal calls, messages popping up on screens, entering inboxes or dropping through mailboxes, getting bawled out at political campaigns, tweeted on social mediaââthe one hailed always recognises that it is really them who is being hailed.â
Althusser labels the drama of interpellation his âlittle theoretical theatre,â and the notion of theatre here is suggestive, full of dialectical resonance. Theatre stage plays involving actors with scripts. These actors assume roles and know how to learn their lines. They memorise them, act these lines out in character. Before them lie audiences, gatherings of people looking on, perhaps innocently, perhaps dangerouslyâdangerously in the sense that they are identifying with the actors. In interpellation, actors and audience become one, get bundled together; you canât differentiate one from the otherâat least in audiencesâ headsâbecause the latter begin to live out the roles theyâre watching. They come to the theatre, Althusser says, really to see themselves, and thatâs why itâs dangerous: itâs precisely how interpellation hails you in life.
Althusser took a keen interest in theatre. While he plainly sees bourgeois theatre like bourgeois life, as a paradigm of interpellation, laden with ideology, he nonetheless understands theatre as part of the solution, too, as educational for not getting taken in by ideology. In this respect, misrecognition becomes a vital arm of political resistance, something Althusser tries to highlight in his articles on Bertolt Brecht.4 Althusser says Brecht revolutionised bourgeois theatre the same way Marx revolutionised bourgeois philosophy. Marx says philosophy shouldnât be contemplative and neither should theatre says Brecht.
It shouldnât be âculinary,â he says, mere entertainment for audiences to drool over the playâs âhero.â In Brechtian âepicâ theatre, there are no heroes, not even in plays like The Life of Galileo and Mother Courage, two of Althusserâs favourites. This is âmaterialistâ theatre. There, the masses make history, not heroes. Brecht wants no object of identificationâeither positive or negativeâbetween spectators and the spectacle, no complicity between the two, no pity or sentimentality, no anger or disgust. Itâs the only sort of alienation that kindled Althusserâs political imaginary: the famous âalienation-effect,â Brechtâs Verfremdungeffektâor V-effektâthe distancing that avoids reifying inter-subjectivity, that counteracts any possible emotional empathy audiences develop with the characters.
Brecht demands cool thinking responses from his audiences, not hot feeling outbursts. He wants to foster critical interpretation, a thought that provokes action. Overthrown are classical ideals of Greek theatre, where the repressed energy of the drama erupts into what Aristotle called catharsisâa stirring emotional release, usually at the playâs finale. It sounds like the din of a Trump rally, its demagogic rage. Brecht wants to snub any fictional triumph, any fear and misery of the Second Term. He interrogates context rather than panders to confabulation. âThe public ought to cease to identify with what theyâre watching,â says Althusser. âThey ought to find a critical position,â take a stand on the outside, not be taken in on the inside. Itâs precisely this critical distance that needs to be carried over into real life, into our diseased life. Like with all viruses, prevention is always better than cure.
***
As Althusser drifted away from the PCF in the late 1970s, Lefebvre drifted back into it. The decade pushed and pulled socialists and communists everywhere, ushering in as much a meltdown of the post-war Left as of post-war capitalism. Gramsci might have called this an interregnum, between a dying past and a new era yet to be born, haunted in the meantime by monsters. For awhile, the Left in France called for unity, for a âUnion of the Leftâ; a popular unity to ward off monsters, between the PCF and the Socialist Party (PS), in solidarity with other Left factions and forcesâavoiding, on the one side, dogmatism and sectarianism within its own ranks, and striving, on the other, to forge an electoral pact, a ballot box socialism.
The European Left was distancing itself from Moscow, abandoning commitment to âdictatorship of the proletariat,â embracing instead so-called âEurocommunismâââthe democratic road to socialism.â The workersâ movement needed to fight for structural reforms, transform the capitalist system by stages, eventually altering it wholesale. Head on confrontation between bourgeoisie and proletariat ought to be avoided; socialism without the consensus of a large majority of the âprogressiveâ population would be impossible. Rather than take the enemyâs fortress by assault, in one fell swoop, Eurocommunists needed to encircle this fortress, undermine it gradually, vote it out, erode its power. Later on, they could seize control, democratise the state.
Althusser thought this a grave tactical error, a betrayal of the working classes, and said so after the Unionâs electoral defeat in 1978; Lefebvre seemed more open, more curious about its exploration, more ready to face reality. Althusser wrote a series of blistering articles in April, 1978, serialised in the newspaper Le monde, about why he thought the Left union had collapsed and âWhat Must Change in the Party.â5 He said the Party had to step out of its own âfortress,â embrace the popular movement, have more faith in the rank and file. âDemocratic centralismâ could only work, Althusser said, if the PCF loosened its absolutist grip on the workersâ movement. Party bigwigs, alas, had been more concerned with defending their institutional privileges against the PS than in allying to combat a national bourgeoisie.
Lefebvre also released a text in 1978âa crucial year in the demise of European Leftâa book with a revealing title: La rĂ©volution nâest plus ce quâelle Ă©tait [The Revolution Isnât What it Was], a dialogical exchange with Catherine Regulier, Lefebvreâs newly-wed and young PCF militant. Althusser is frequently pilloried by Lefebvre; Regulier usually sides with her Party comrade in opposition to her husband, making the conversation particularly fascinating because of its tangled loyalties. Like Althusser, Lefebvre disagrees with Gramsci: the Party isnât a Modern Prince; Stalin put paid to such imagery. Yet rather than orchestrate âdemocratic centralism,â Lefebvre wants to develop and generalise âautogestion,â a worker self-management, pushing the Party to accept more decentralisation; power needed devolving to local communes; more coordinated direct action required fostering at ground level. Lefebvre, in effect, sought a democratic line between Party and state, wishing both would wither away.
Ătienne Balibar, a former student and confidant of Althusser, and co-author with his teacher of Reading Capital, told me via email that Lefebvre and Althusser actually encountered each other during this fraught period. They met along with other Marxist theoreticians (like Christine Buci-Glucksmann and Jean-Marie Vincent) at Lefebvreâs apartment on rue Rambuteau (overlooking the Pompidou Centre). Balibar says they were âprivate meetingsâ [rĂ©unions privĂ©es], organised by another ex-Althusser student Nicos Poulantzas, whose idea was âto try and reunite Marxist intellectuals and relaunch, if possible, Leftist debate and the Union of the Left in distress [LâUnion de la gauche en perdition].â6
âLefebvre was old,â recalls Balibar, âbut very alert and a charming conversationalist.â He wanted the Left âto bury the old hatchets,â to overcome its internal differences and disagreements, have everyone make peace with one another. Maybe he was recalling what Lenin said about Marxists and anarchists? That there was nine-tenths similarity and one-tenth difference. Didnât the same go for humanists and anti-humanists? âAlthusser was often ill and absent in those days,â Balibar remembers. âHe came a few times to the meetings without saying much, sometimes saying nothing at all.â âLefebvre,â says Balibar, âtold me that the Presses Universitaires de France had commissioned him to do a book on âMarx Todayâ. âWhy donât we do it together?â he asked me. Like an idiot I refused, under the pretext that the deadline was too short for me, and that I write much slower than he does. To this day, I regret not doing it.â7
Lefebvreâs and Althusserâs work over that decade, from differing perspectives, tried to valorise for the Left a capitalist state in crisis. Could a unified Left leverage state power away from a disgruntled Right? Could it do so in the streets, in the factories, and through the ballot box? Could forces within the state be modified by organised pressure from the outside? Could pressure from the outside not only transform the inside but actually become that inside? âOn sâengage,â Althusser used to say, âet puis on voit.â And yet, after engaging, after jumping into the fray, what one saw was a dramatic power shift, a transition and renewal in the reverse direction. It was the Right who got its act together, who closed ranks, whose class power âcondensed,â just as the Leftâs fell apart, as its unity fractured into disunity.
By the mid-1980s, a lot of ideas about popular unity and democratising the state, about Eurocommunism triumphing, collapsed, got rejectedâalmost before the votes were cast. Somehow its programme had overly compromised; or else hadnât compromised enough. It was as if the Left didnât know whether it was coming or going, having no more legs to stand on. It had kicked away both the Party and the People, hobbled lame. Still, unlike Britain and the US, âthe Leftâ did nonetheless triumph in France, in 1981, under François Mitterrandâs Socialist Party; yet victory soon turned Pyrrhic, as its âleftistâ policies began drawing straight from the Rightâs playbook. By then, too, in a gentrifying Paris, an octogenarian Lefebvre had been evicted from his rental on rue Rambuteau and a depressed Althusser had strangled his beloved wife, HĂ©lĂšne, in a moment of âtemporary insanity,â ending his days as a public figure. Poulantzas, meanwhile, had freaked out at a friendâs apartment, throwing himself out of the window in an impulsive suicidal defenestration.
Suddenly, the âNew Rightâ set off on its long march, telling us there is no such thing as society anymore, only individuals and families. From struggling to ensure a providential state, now there was apparently no more state, not a public state for people anyway, only one preparing the political terrain for free market entrepreneurialism. Thus arose an awkward predicament for progressive people, especially for Marxist theoreticians: those items of âcollective consumptionâ so vital for reproduction of the relations of production, so indispensable for propping up demand in the economy and for satisfying working class needsâpublic housing and infrastructure, hospitals and collectively consumed goods and servicesâwere getting cast aside. How could this be? What once appeared essential ingredients for capitalismâs continued reproduction, for its long term survival, now turned out to be only contingent after all.
The Left has never really come to terms with a seismic tremor that registered big digits on the neoliberal Richter Scale. The 1980s bid adieu to social democratic reformism, to an age when the public sector was the solution to capitalismâs woes and the private sector the problem. Henceforth the former needed negating, Right ideologues argued; the private sector was the solution and a shot and bloated public sector the problem. State bureaucrats dishing out items of collective consumption through some principle of redistributive justice gave way to reality in which the market ruled. Writ large was the beginning of the privatisation of everything, of an ideology of possessive individualism. âFreedomâ became its tagline: free markets, free trade, free choice, freedom to consume, freedom to do oneâs own thing, freedom not to care about other peopleâs freedom.
Successive generations have been force-fed this ideology of freedom, treating anything public, any realm of necessity, with suspicion, as shoddy and inefficient, as something symbolising unfreedom. Now, itâs no longer an ideological category: itâs embedded in peopleâs brains, a belief system that teaches us how to forget, how to turn our backs on the public realm and ergo on any social contract. Maybe for good reason: the public state has been hollowed out to such a degree that it is shoddy. Its core functionsâthe planning and organisation of public servicesâhave been outsourced to private consultants and contractors whoâve delivered little yet raked in much.
And as pandemic raged, countries whoâd hollowed out their states most of all fast discovered they had neither the hardware capacity nor the software know-how to deal with a massive societal problem. So they doled out millions to private consultant âexpertsâ like McKinsey who apparently did. When, in Britain, the latter instigated a National Health Service (NHS) test and trace system that hardly worked, we realised these âexperts,â too, were clueless. COVID-19 has exposed the shortcomings of the privatised state, of the incompetence of private enterprise addressing public healthâand of how public health challenges arenât resolvable by individuals and families alone.
Thereâs plenty of collective necessity, of course, dealing with a global pandemic. But collective necessity can only work if people recognise the state as âdemocratic,â know good government from bad. These days, in populist nations, democracy seems like a vision from another planet. We might call these uncivil states because people there have lost their sense of duty to one another. Weâve been kidded by demagogues into thinking weâre all free agents capable of doing what we like, and if we canât then itâs someone elseâs fault. The European Unionâs? Big governmentâs? Rarely big businessâs. Private inclinations have run roughshod over public interests, cults of personality have gone viral. Maybe intelligent people, inspired by some Brechtian V-effekt, might one day acknowledge society again, might distance themselves from ruling class lures and lies. Perhaps then weâll see how we can be freer if each of us admits that we are part of a public culture in desperate need of collective repair, that the goal of socialist democracy is to fight to reclaim public power.
En route, we might also remember Marx, who insisted that real freedom came though addressing necessity. âFreedom can only consist in socialised man,â Marx said, âwhen associated producers rationally regulate their metabolism with Nature.â âA shortening of working day is the basic prerequisite for freedom,â he thought. Life blossoms forth on such a basis, he said. Freedom without necessity is yet more bourgeois claptrap, another ideological ruse to perpetuate its class dominance. âThe bourgeoisie lives in the ideology of freedom,â Althusser tell us, and makes us live in it, too, forces its concept down our throats. But real freedom is hard when you have to worry about making the next rent check, when you wonder if your job will be there tomorrow, or what happens if you get sick. Free choice means practically nothing when youâre financially enslaved. Freedom here isnât very humanist. Indeed, when it comes to anti-humanism, capitalism has got Marxism licked any day.
Notes
- â© See, especially, Dialectical Materialism (1939), Lefebvreâs humanist rejoinder to Stalinâs Historical and Dialectical Materialism, published in Moscow a year earlier.
- â© See Althusserâs For Marx (1965), the best introduction to his anti-humanist Marxism.
- â© We might remember that even Marxâs abstract reasoning is concrete. Marx is weary of abstract abstractions, calling them in the Grundrisse âchaotic conceptions.â In a way, Marx would have been sceptical of epidemiologistsâ scale of âpopulation.â âPopulation,â Marx says, is an abstract abstraction, âif I leave out the classes of which it is composed. These classes in turn are an empty phrase if I am not familiar with the elements on which they rest. E.g. wage labour, capital, etc. These latter presuppose exchange, division of labour, prices, etc.â When we follow Marxâs concrete logic, we can see more clearly how the COVID pandemic doesnât just affect the population, but strikes different populations, strikes them unevenly and unequally, subject to positioning in the wage-relation and division of labour. Here we might add different races, too, and different classes of those races.
- â© Two instances are âThe Piccolo Teatro,â a discussion of Bertolazzi alongside Brecht, which Althusser included in For Marx; and another, âSur Brecht et Marx,â in Ăcrits philosophiques et politiques â tome II (1997).
- â© New Left Review translated and republished Althusserâs missives as a standalone essay (see NLR, No.109, May-June 1978).
- â© Even if little of practicality emerged from these meetings, protagonists did help pioneer a very interesting, if short-lived, theoretical journal called Dialectiques; between 1973 and 1981, 33 issues appeared, full of wonderful material that still inspires. Both Lefebvre and Althusser feature within its now-yellowing leaves, yin and yang opposites of a truly dialectical Marxism for what were truly dialectical times.
- â© Ironically, the book, Ătre Marxiste Aujourdâhui [To be a Marxist Today], would only materialise years later, in 1986, co-written with Patrick Tort, a strange homage to Georg LukĂĄcs. The focus was a conference at Parisâs Hungarian Institute from 1955, celebrating LukĂĄcsâs 70th birthday, an opportunity for Lefebvre to critique as well as champion his old Hegelian-Marxist colleague. If Balibar regrets passing up on joint-authorship, we can only regret not reading what might have been.